During the huge public discourse, especially in the aftermath of 11 September 2001, Muslim mind-set toward modernity frequently came into question. A whole theology bas came into being on the question whether Islam and modernity are compatible to each other. Neither the question nor the arguments are new. Similar debates arose in the nineteenth century when the Western nations colonized Muslim lands. Unfortunately, the terror and violence that accompanied modernization distorted the image of modernity. Today also, the debate on modernity is deflected by the political events that are marred by violence, terror and destruction. The focus of debate shifts the emphasis from the quest of modernity to political concerns. It is in the wake of such concerns that modernity is defined in universalistic and essentialist terms and Islam and Muslims are characterized as incompatible to modernity.
I find it more fateful that some Muslims have this thesis with religious zeal and reject modernity as a Western ideology. To me, Modernity is an historical process and an outcome of a cumulative contribution by all human cultures towards the present stage of development in human history. It is in this sense that there is not one but several modernities; various traditions transform into varying modernities. Second, the Western and Muslim societies were not always as self-righteous as they are today. In fact in the early nineteenth century when the Western nations landed on the shores of Muslim lands, they were fascinated by the mystique of the orient.
In India, for instance, Warren Hastings chose the title of Nawwab Bahadur for himself. English historians are fond of telling the stories of ’English Nabobs’ who lived and dressed like Indian Muslims. More than 500 Europeans mastered Urdu language to the extent that they are acclaimed as Urdu Poets by the historians of Urdu literature. The’ English residents of Delhi frequently visited Shah Abdul Aziz the famous scholar in the city. James Skinner requested amulets from Shah Abdul Aziz for the health of her children. Some of Shah’s contemporaries raised questions about one of the Shah’s relative who had taken employment with the British. Shah could however, satisfy these inquirers that Islam did not forbid relations with the English because they were people of the book. He could also explain that a Muslim could sit and eat with the English. I am not saying that the Muslims and the English ad no problems. Of course, on bath sides there were also people who were reluctant, but the significant fart is that an Islamic scholar and a religious leader could justify cultural relations between the Muslims and the Westerners. Today also, the number of Muslim citizens, not immigrants and temporary labour, in the Western countries is significantly higher than ever. On the other hand, the presence of Western culture in Muslim societies is equally evident in daily urban life, in schools, in media and in various cultural aspects.
In the following pages, I would like to analyze three aspects in Islamic tradition that have provided Islamic intellectual tradition the cultural flexibility sufficient to cape with contemporary challenges: secular sciences, jihad, pluralism and human rights.
SECULAR SCIENCES
We may say that
Islam’s encounter with the West began
quite early when Greek intellectual
tradition carne to the Muslim society in
the ninth century under the Abbasid
caliph Mamun. It generated a debate
about the legitimacy of studying Greek
sciences but the fart that a movement in
favour of Greek sciences continued to
flourish throughout the Islamic history
is by itself an evidence of Islam’ s
cultural compatibility. This movement
generated a controversy deep into the
religious issues about the nature of the
Qur’anic revelation and the role of
reason. Opposition to this movement
finally triumphed as “orthodoxy”, but
not without recognizing the necessity of
studying Greek secular sciences. Al-Ghazali,
a twelfth century Muslim thinker, who
wrote a refutation of this philosophical
movement in Islam and who separated
purely “religious” from other sciences,
was also responsible for introducing
Greek logic in the “pure religious
sciences”. The science of Kalam
(roughly, Islamic theology) born out of
the need to refute foreign ideas was
regarded as the science of Da’wa and
Jihad. This science relied heavily on
Greek logic, rhetoric and metaphysics.
The science of Kalam
continued to engage Muslim philosophers
in the controversy about reason and
revelation in Islam. The controversy
came to be known in Europe through Latin
translations of Averroes. Islamic
philosophical investigations into
revelation attracted the European
religious thought to appreciate the
rationalist tradition.
No doubt,
opposition in the Muslim community to
rational sciences continued, but at the
same time a considerable number of Greek
texts or their Arabic adaptations on
Astronomy, Geography, Calculus,
Mechanics etc., became part of the
Muslim religious curriculum. They were
called “Ma’qulat” (rational sciences) in
contrast to pure religious text studies,
which were called “Manqulat”. Abu’l
Hasan Ali Nadwi, a twentieth century
Muslim educationist in India, in bis
book on Islamic encounter with the West,
admired the Muslim way of adapting Greek
sciences to the need of Muslim society
in the ninth century as a model for
assimilation of modern Western sciences
into Muslim education today.
The Greek sciences, especially logic and metaphysics shaped the Muslim worldview, which Muslim modernists like Jamal al-Din Afghani and Muhammad Iqbal found responsible for Muslim stagnation. Iqbal argued that the classical Greek thought of statism was opposite to the Qur’anic dynamism. It is paradoxical that some religious institutions of learning insisted in the nineteenth and twentieth century on preserving traditional curricula which include some of the Greek secular sciences, but refused to introduce new sciences. The situation is gradually changing and these institutions are adopting new secular sciences as well. Often, the modernists have argued that modern sciences are in fact Muslim sciences which came to Europe in the middle ages.
In the twentieth
century the dispute about whether
Muslims should learn Western sciences
was settled with reference to Da ’wa and
jihad. Some Algerian students approached
Mufti Abdul Aziz b. Muhammad b. al-Siddiq
in Morocco in 1985. They narrated that
some Ulama forbade studying secular
sciences because they would influence
young Muslim minds in favour of the
West. The students asked if migration to
Europe for work and for studies was
permissible. Mufti al-Siddiq recited the
Qur’anic verse “Let not the unbelievers
think that they have surpassed, they
could not be weakened. Against them make
ready your strength to the utmost of
your power (8: 59-60). He explained that
the verse requires Muslims to travel to
the West and learn the sciences and
technology that gives west the
superiority. Muslim must learn these
sciences to build their strength.
I
must add that this verse is very basic
to the modern Jihad discourse. It is
used to justify the continuous
obligation of jihad. Here, the Mufti
employed it to justify modernization of
Islamic education. The verse is also
employed to justify the need for
modernization of society, state and
particularly the Muslim armies.
JIHAD
The above mentioned
verse was also cited to justify
modernization of Ottoman armies, warfare
and weapons. A Muslim jurist Mufti
Shihabuddin Alusi (d. 1853) was
reluctant to allow the use of firearms.
It was, for him, against the
conventional warfare. Other jurists
disagreed because it would put Muslim
army in a weak position. Resistance to
seeking help from non-Muslims,
especially hiring non-Muslim army
instructors to train Muslim soldiers was
also easily dismissed on similar
grounds.
Rashid Rida (d. 1935)
insisted on modernizing Muslim armies.
How could Muslims remain restricted to
the use of arrows and swords against an
enemy who used guns and rifles? To
Rashid Rida, the Qûr’anic verse obliged
Muslims to build up strength superior to
their enemies. No modern Muslim scholar
is today opposed to the modernization or
Westernization of Muslim armies.
In
fact, the directors of a panel of
researchers in the Third Mediterranean
Social and Political Research Meeting,
Florence March 2002 proposed to explore
the reference to jihad as justification
of modernizing armies in the following
words:”The study of the founding
discourses and the ideological
controversies that presided over the
creation of modern armies raises
questions about the foundations of Nizam
legitimating, in the light of the
generic mission of Jihad”.
The notion of Jihad was thus quite naturally used for justifying modernization and reform of Muslim society. The principle of jihad was extended even to things and matters, which were other wise, prohibited. It opened space for modernization of Muslim society, especially legitimizing women’s place for women in public as nurses and teachers.
The principle of Jihad also gave birth to the movement of reform in Muslim societies in eighteenth century and afterwards. These movements condemned social practices that promoted superstition, extravagance, pessimism and annihilism. They also initiated reforms within Islam that challenged the religious authority of traditional schools of Islamic law and the Sufi orders. Some of these movements in Africa revolted against the traditional political systems and established Islamic states.
The principle of Jihad became the mainstay for the struggle for independence against the colonial rule. The traditional Ulama who were reluctant to join politics were obliged to participate in the struggle in the name of Jihad. The Western capitalism also found Jihad useful in the cold war. It became the rallying point against communism and socialism. The word Mujahidin became a common word in the Western societies. Alliance of the Mujahidin with the West introduced to them new ideas and technology and the need modernize Muslim societies.
The need for change of political system with militant force led these Mujahidin groups to reconstruct a new ideology of Jihad. It advocated militant solutions of political conflicts. After the collapse of the Soviet Union, the West was no longer interested in Jihad or Mujahidin. The rise of this extremist view of Jihad led to its privatization and sectarian violence.
PRIVATE JIHAD
One of the many
setbacks to Islamic law during the
colonial period is its privatization.
Unfortunately, this privatization
continued after the independence of
Muslim countries. The idea has become so
entrenched in the modern Islamic
thinking that it has gravely damaged the
conception of its role as a public and
international law. I will illustrate
this point with reference to a
university dissertation on Jihad.
’Ali b. Nafi’ al-Ulyani, in his doctoral
thesis in 1984, defines Jihad as
follows: “The word in simple usage means
killing infidels for the supremacy of
the word of God and cannot be
interpreted otherwise unless there is an
evidence for a different meaning”.
(117).
The aims and objectives of
Jihad, according to him, include making
people submit to God alone, protection
of Islamic state, killing infidels, and
terrorizing infidels and to humiliate
them, among other things.
In his words: “In
modern times, some persons trained by
the colonialists and who have chosen the
life of humiliation and helplessness to
that of honor and Jihad, have doubted
the role of Jihad in the spread of
Islam. They assume that it was due to
peaceful preaching without Jihad that
Islam spread in the early period and it
is the best way today as well. They have
rather extended their argument to claim
that spread of Islam by Jihad is an
allegation against Islam that must be
defended. Their teachers in this
intellectual distortion are the
Orientalists. The most famous among them
is the evil-minded Orientalist Thomas
Arnold who wrote a book entitled
“Preaching of Islam”. This book was
aimed to kill the spirit of Jihad among
the Muslims”. (261).
Al-’Ulyani
describes that Jihad is generally
divided into two types. (1). Jihad al-talab
wa’l ibtida, which means to calI upon (tatallub)
the infidels in their land to Islam, and
fighting (killing) them if they do not
submit to the rule of Islam. This type
is regarded as fard kifaya (collective
duty) and becomes individual duty, when
there is a general declaration of war or
the Imam calls for it (124). (2)
Al-jihad al-difa ’i (defensive Jihad) is
the second type, which is regarded as
fard ’ayn. He questions this division
and concludes that Jihad difa ’i
(defensive Jihad) is a bid’a munkara (a
reprehensible innovation).
He then condemns the following as those who committed this heresy of defining Jihad to be defensive: Abd al-Wahhab al-Khallaf, Mahmud Shaltut, Muhammad Abd Allah Diraz, Wahba Zuhayli, Muhammad Izza Darwaza, Hamid Sultan; Ali Ali Mansur, Jamal al-Banna, Abd al-Khaliq al-Nawawi, Muhammad Ra’fat Uthman. I need not to stress that all of them are well known religious thinkers and are respected for their scholarship.
This trend of
privatization can be traced to the
inclusion of Amr bi ’l-ma ’ruf in the
books on Islamic Criminal Law. I
illustrate here with reference to ’Abdul
Qadir ’Awda’s (shahid 1954) Al-tashri’
al-Jina’i al-Islami, which has become
popular text
in law faculties.’ Awda
argues that Jihad, Zakat, and
enforcement of Hudud (penalties) are not
only duties of a state but also of an
individual. It is an individual
obligation to use physical force to
correct evil. He, therefore, allows an
individual to
inflict punishment on
convicted criminals. He argues that
enforcement of Hudud is an obligation
for the Muslim Umma as a whole, not only
for the state. The Islamic legal
principle of Ihdar (violability, meaning
loss of rights and protection) is not
available for non-Muslims and apostates.
Islamic law provides legal protection
only on the basis of Iman (faith) and
Aman (pact), ’Awda maintains. The life
and property of a non-Muslim are
violable if he or his people have no
agreement of protection with Muslims. An
apostate, a Muslim who forsakes Islam,
also loses all rights and becomes
violable. According to ’Awda, any Muslim
can kill a Harbi (a non-Muslim without a
pact of protection) or an apostate
without criminal liability.
’A wda
extends the law of violability also to
persans sentenced in the Hudud crimes.
If a Muslim kills a person convicted for
Zina, rebellion and robbery, he is not
criminally liable for murder.
’A wda’s concept of the principle of violability (Ihdar) of life differs significantly from the classical jurists. For instance, according to Hanafi School, a person who kills an apostate must be punished for taking law into his own hands (’Awda 1979,635). The Maliki school calls for punishment in this case in addition to diya (compensation for murder (’Awda 1979, 635). Similarly, according to Maliki, Hanafi and Hanbali schools, the murder of a persan convicted for Zina may not be treated as homicide but may be punished for taking law in his own hands. The Shafi ’i jurists regard the person criminally liable for murder (’ Awda 1979,639).
’A wda disagrees with the views of these schools and justifies, in a sense, taking law into one’s own hand: ” If courts do not sentence an apostate, as it commonly happens in Muslim countries today, these institutions have no authority to punish a person who kills an apostate (in obedience to Shari ’a). The killer cannot be accused of violating the authority of these institutions because they have not undertaken the responsibility of enforcing Shari ’a laws. Since they have forsaken Shari ’a, individuals cannot be held responsible if they implement these laws on their own” (’Awda 1979, 636).
Muslim orthodoxy condemned these views as religious extremism. Muslim governments started taking legal actions against these movements. These groups were however too well organized and financially too strong to be controlled by Muslim governments. While the governments in Egypt, Pakistan and Saudi Arabia banned these extremist Jihad organizations, the Ulama were engaged in distinguishing jihad from extremism, militarism, violence and terror.
These inner controversies in the Muslim world on Jihad came to be known to the world only after the 11 September. ln fact this debate was already going on in Muslim societies. That is why the condemnation of the terrorist attack was immediate and unanimous. Sa’id Ramadan al-Buti, in bis Al-Jihad fi ’I Islam (1993) rejected the use of Jihad for political change, revolution, and to change the government. The right Islamic legal term for this activity was Baghy (revolt and disobedience). Islamic law allowed revolt if it could be justified rationally. The use of violence and force without specific political objective was also distinct from Jihad. Islamic law called it Haraba (terror) which was a crime and condemnable.
In Iran the Shi’i thinker Mutahhari refuted the extremist argument that Jihad was an absolute obligation and that the Muslims must always be at war with non-Muslims. Jihad was a positive concept. That is why in Iran the term Jihad was used for social reconstruction. Jihad Sazindagi (1979) aimed at modernization of rural Iran, roads, schools, health, electricity etc.
PLURALISM
Pluralism favours the
freedom of individual. It questions the
traditional monopoly of certain persons,
groups or institutions to prescribe
ethical values authoritatively.
Pluralism derives ifs legitimacy and
acceptance by justifying universal
values in local contexts. This is
particularly significant in today’s
world of globalism. A powerful group,
nation or country cannot impose its
values on others without generating the
feelings of frustration and resentment
among the weaker groups and countries.
Globalism can succeed only on the basis
of ethical pluralism.
Generally,
Islamic law is regarded as the only
Islamic moral tradition. Islam as a
moral tradition bas never been
monolithic (1). Quite early in its
history, it developed several approaches
to moral issues. These approaches vary
in their sources of
authority,
methods of interpretations and emphasis.
They sometimes oppose one another but
often continue to function side by side,
even complementing each other. It is
therefore well in order to review, even
if briefly, these various moral
traditions in Islam.
The Hadith
literature reflects a very significant
moral tradition. It offers the Prophet
Muhammad and his companions as models
for moral behaviour. This tradition does
refer to the pre-Islamic tribal Sunna
but only to elaborate its approval or
disapproval by early Muslims. The
outstanding aspect of this ethical
tradition is that it is essentially
religious and authenticity oriented.
However, the fact that this tradition
produced dozens of compendia, each of
them accepted by Muslims as
authoritative, stresses the principle of
ethical pluralism within the tradition
itself.
Pre-Islamic tribal
values like manliness, honor,
forbearance and tolerance were part of
the Arab Sunna tradition that operated
at the level of custom and usage in the
literary moral tradition called Adab.
The Adab tradition represents a humanist
moral approach to morality. Most
probably, writings in this tradition
were initiated by Ibn Muqaffa’
(d.
756), and carried on by several other
writers like Ibn Qutayba (d. 889), al-Mawardi,
(d. 1058) and Qalqashandi (d. 1418). The
Adab tradition expresses itself in the
literary genre. The Adab literature is
composed as guides for the rulers or
civil servants, or mirrors for the
prince. It lays down the ideal model
behaviour for them. This tradition is
more open as it derives its ethical
values from diverse sources: pre-Islamic
Arabic as well as Persian literature,
Qur’an, history of Islam, ancient
Persian history and Greek and Indian
Literature. Ibn Muqaffa’ translated into
Arabic Kalila wa Dimna, a book on moral
stories originating in India. The Adab
tradition continues in arts and
literature but also as etiquette
literature providing code of ethics for
various professions such as
musicians(2).
The philosophical tradition in Islam dealt with the ethical issues on a more abstract level than the Adab tradition. One of the essential questions with which this tradition engaged itself was about the question of ethical obligation and its origins. The issue was whether it was only religion that defined rights and obligations or the human reason on its own could also differentiate between ethically good and bad. The Muslim philosophers explored the nature, of Prophethood, revelation, role of reason and other such themes. From Ibn Sina (d. 1037) to Ibn Rushd (d. 1198), the Muslim philosophers generally argued that there was no conflict between reason and revelation. The most interesting example of the discussion of this problem is the treatises by the title Hayy bin Yaqzan (3) (The Living, son of Awake) by Ibn Sina and Ibn Tufayl (d. 1185). Ibn Tufayl’s story presents Hayy as a human child growing up on an island among animals, without any contact with humans. By instinct and experience he develops a moral code for himself. Later, he finds out that his moral values were not different from the religious values in the neighboring island with human habitat. Jurist philosophers like Abu Ishaq al-Shatibi (4) and Shah Waliullah (5) also hold that hum an reason reaches similar conclusions during the absence of revelation.
Rushdi Rashid has
argued that Algebra presented a new
rationality that provided a new
intellectual strategy to find new
solutions. It opened new vistas into the
realm of the impossible. Algebra,
employing the multidisciplinary methods
of geometry and arithmetic, demonstrated
that approximate and impossible
solutions could also be true solutions
of a problem.
The philosophical
tradition developed a system of
practical or applied ethics that came to
be known as Akhlaq. It received its
recognition as Islamic ethics proper as
early as eleventh century. It is a
synthesis of pre-Islamic Arab moral
values, Qur’anic teachings and has
Persian, Indian and Greek elements in
it. Miskawayh’s (d. 1030) Tahdhib al-Akhlaq
offers a comprehensive and systematic
treatment of ethical values in this
tradition. It is quite obviously
influenced by Greek ethical literature.
Miskawayh explains that Greek ethics is
more in accord with Islamic teachings
than the pre-Islamic Arab morality.
Jalal al-Diu al-Dawwani (d. 1501) and
Nasir al-Diu alTusi (d. ) followed
Miskawayh in their writings on ethics.
Their books, popularly known as and
respectively, were used as textbooks in
the religious institutions.
The Sufi
moral tradition is more popular than the
other Islamic moral traditions. The
Sufis were critical of the literal and
exoteric approach to obligations by the
jurists and theologians. Al- Harith al-Muhasibi
(d. 857) wrote Kitab al-ri ’ava fi huquq
Allah (The book of observance of the
rights of God). He treats ethical
obligations as surrender to the will of
God. He speaks of moral values such as
Taqwa (fear of God), Tawba (retum to
God), and Mahabba (love) etc. Muhasibi
stresses abiding by the laws of
prescription and prohibition in the
Qur’an and Sunna, but he stresses on a
more conscious effort to contraI the
self from its propensity toward evil.
Ghazali (d.llll) also followed Miskawayh
in his ethical writings. His books on
ethics, namely Ihva ’Ulum al-Din and
Kimivai Sa ’adat have been more popular
among Muslim readers than bis other
works.
The Sufis became more and more
critical of legal and theological
approach to obligations in later local
traditions. The folk literature stresses
on inner and humanist meanings of
obligations, and on tolerance, love and
sincerity.
Kalam (theology) is another tradition that dealt with the moral questions. This tradition also came to engage very early with the question whether the ethical values of good and bad were known only by revelation and religion or human reason can also discover them. The Mu’tazila school maintained that the ethical values were rational and the revelation never contradicted them. The Mu’tazila developed an entire system of theology and jurisprudence on this basis. They believed in the principle of justice to the extent that they argued that it was an obligation even for God. The revelation, specifically the Qur’an, was not sempitermal because it conformed to the findings of human reason. The Mu’tazila came into conflict with other Muslims, especially the Hadith groups who accused them of denying Divine Attributes. Asha’ira, a group of theologians that broke away from the Mu’tazila denounced the theology of human reason. The Mu’tazila lost the caliph al support they had in the initial period and other groups gained strength. The Kalam tradition, however, is not monolithic; it also developed multiple voices. It was not pluralist in the strict sense as each group c1aimed authenticity only for itself.
Fiqh (legal ethics)
developed initially as multiple local
customary legal traditions. The
plurality of views in the Fiqh
traditions is proverbial. The Hadith
tradition questioned the authenticity of
Fiqh traditions and described it as mere
opinions (ra ’y) as opposed to the
Hadith which was based on scientific
knowledge (’ilm). The Fiqh traditions
produced more than nineteen schools, all
of them recognizing each other’s legal
validity. The multiplicity of views
continues within the schools and is
regarded as a blessing. The principle of
legal reasoning (ijtihad) encourages
difference of opinion considered
religiously rewardable even in case of
error. Adherence to these different
schools of law is reflected in the
diverse personallaws in Muslim
societies.
It is significant to
note that the caliphs in early Islamic
history were quite apprehensive about
the conflicting views of the Muslim
jurists that produced diverse court
judgements. Several Abbasi caliphs and
later other Muslim rulers tried to unify
laws. Resistance to such attempts often
came from the Muslim jurists themselves.
They feared that such attempts would
mean state interference in this
tradition. They wanted to preserve their
freedom. They did consider their works
enforceable by the state, but they never
agreed to codify them as state laws. As
a result, Muslim societies have been
continuously practicing legal pluralism
before the advent of modern nation
state. The rural and tribal areas
continued their local customary laws,
sometimes even non-Muslim laws (as for
example in Mughal and Ottoman villages).
ln cities as well, there were different
type of courts. The courts of complaints
differed from ordinary
courts even in
their procedural laws. Different state
institutions like police also had their
own legal system and procedures. The
Hisba (public sensor) courts had
jurisdiction in business ethics in the
market as weIl as in offences against
public marals.
Fiqh soon came to
stand for Shari’a (Divine law) and
defined moral as well as legal
obligations. This position of the Fiqh
came about ,mostly with the jurists
functioning as Muftis. A Mufti, even
today, may be asked about any matter
under the sun and he is supposed to
explain God’s law on the points in
question. Consequently, Fiqh
assumed
a dominating position. A Mufti’s
response, called Fatwa, offered a social
construction of Shari’ a, as most often
it referred to a concrete social
question. Fatwa reviews a moral practice
with reference to the Shari’a ideal.
Most often we find Muftis also adjusting
ideals to practice in view of the
prevailing social conditions.
These
practices are frequently assimilated in
the tradition in such a way that they
are sometimes hard to distinguish. I
shall refer to some fatwas to illustrate
this point in the next section.
To conclude, Islam as
a moral tradition favours pluralism on
two bases. Firstly because it appeals to
human reason. The Qur’an attaches
pivotal significance to individual
rational choice and responsibility.
“There is no coercion in religion. The
truth stands out clear from Error” …
(Qur’an, 2:256). “By the soul, and the
order given it, He has inspired it to
its wrong and to its good” (Qur’an, 91:
7-8). “To each is a goal to which he
turns it. Then strive for what is good…”
(2: 178). “Say, ’The Truth is from your
Lord’, then believe who wills and deny
who wills (18: 29). The emphasis here is
not so much that ethical values are
rational and scientific but that they
are reasonable to be understood as such
by humans. Since the level of
understanding may differ from person to
person and from community to community
multiplicity of views is inevitable.
The second basis of pluralism is social
acceptance of these values. This basis
also regulates the dissent. The Qur’an
calls good Ma’ruf (well kn,own) and evil
Munkar (rejected), which points to the
fact that normativity is based on social
acceptance or rejection. The social
dialectics develop the acceptable
definition of ethical values.
HUMAN RIGHTS
There are two Muslim
declarations on Human rights: The
Universal Islamic Declaration of Human
Rights (UIDHR) issued by the Islamic
Council, a non government Muslim
organization in London, in 1981 and the
Cairo Declaration of Human Rights
inIslam (CDHRI), issuedby the Foreign
Ministers of Muslim
countries in
Cairo in 1990. Compared with the
Universal Declaration of Human Rights
1948, the area of common grounds between
the Muslim documents and UDHR is larger
than that where they differ. The two
documents share respectively 20 and 14
themes of rights with those mentioned in
the UDHR. It is also significant to note
that
UIDHR, which is a non-state
declaration, has more in common with
UDHR than CDHRI which is a state
document.
The themes where the Muslim
documents differ with UDHR are as
follows: Freedom of thought and
expression, protection of life, penal
laws, marnage, and holding of public
office. On the whole, I find in both
documents an attempt to come closer to
the global community. The same trend is
reflected in numerous Muslim writings on
Human rights which stress on a larger
area of common perspectives (6). They
suggest uniformity with an emphasis on
diversity. ln other words, diversity in
these writings stresses the possibility
of localizing the universals. Here,
universal rights are mentioned in
Islamic language, often claiming that
Islam is the first religion to award
these human rights.
In my view, these
debates on Islam and human rights have
been missing a very essential point: the
ethical aspect of the human rights. A
movement for global ethics hopes to fill
this gap. I find Muslim anxieties
emerging from the perspectives of
national sovereignty and security on the
one band and from religious and cultural
perspective on the other band. Most
human rights are restricted or violated
by Muslim governments in the name of
national security, and they object to
international criticism as a violation
of their national sovereignty. Concern
for national security
cannot justify
violation of the freedom and dignity of
man. However, when the US, Britain, and
Israel, to name a few current examples,
violate human rights and justify them in
the name of national security, the
question arises: what is global,
national interest or ethical principles?
UDHR document is quite ambivalent; it
stresses the universality of hum an
rights as well as the principle of the
sovereignty of the nation and nation
state. I agree with Myer that it is a
challenge of methodology, but it is not
only for Muslims. It is a challenge for
us all to define and apply human rights
as truly universal principles, and not
as an instrument for cultural, economic
and political hegemony of the powerful.
For this purpose Human Rights have to be
rooted in ethics that protects the weak
and the poor also.
There is a wide range of diversity among Muslim scholars on human rights. This diversity is informed by a very complex understanding of tradition and change. One notices three major trends in the Muslim writings on this subject : Neo conservative, Islamic modernists and Progressive Muslims.
Neo-conservative
Muslim thinkers that emerged in probably
1970s and their full impact was visible
in 1980s. They are doser to conservative
in sharing same cultural values. They
differ with them however, because they
have developed a new jurisprudence and
they frequently use modern Western
thought categories presenting and
justifying their conservative values.
Abdul Wahhab Abdul Aziz al-Shishani’s
book on Human Rights in Islam represents
this group. Shishani speaks about a
major paradigm shift in the concept of
state in the modern period. This concept
stresses protecting the rights of the
individual (7). Revising the
authoritative sources of Islamic law
Shishani adds six more to the classical
four: the Qur’an, the Sunna (the rulings
and practice of Prophet Muhammad), Qiyas
(analogies from the above two), and Ijma’
(consensus of the jurists). Normativity
of Islamic laws is grounded on the
principles that suit human nature; they
are not based on customs of a people(8).
This explanation illustrates this
neo-conservatism. Unlike traditional
jurists, who regard revelation by itself
normative, this new trend justifies it
on the basis of its suitability to human
nature. AIso, unlike modemists, this
trend dismisses historicity and social
process as an explanation for the
development of Islamic law. Also, unlike
traditional conservatives who insist on
continuing the legal tradition of the
schools of law, this new trend calls for
Ijtihad (legal reasoning beyond the
confines of schools).
In contrast to
conservatives, Islamic modernists
believe that modernity is compatible to
Islam. Like Neo-conservatives they
stress on Ijtihad against strict
adherence to the Islamic legal
tradition, but they define it as
“reinterpretation” or reconstruction
(9). They believe that the
classicallegal doctrines were product of
historical and social contexts and
therefore there is a need for reform.
Their methodology consists of explaining
the historical and social contexts of
the basic Islamic texts, including the
Qur’an, and to reinterpret them in view
of modern needs.
Progressive Muslims
describe themselves as distinct from
conservative and liberals because they
regard Muslim liberals have relativised
Islamic values and operate in a
framework informed by the Western
impact. They are committed to three
basics: social justice, pluralism and
gender justice.(10) A progressive Muslim
engages with
tradition in light of
modernity, but at the same s/he is
critical of the arrogance of modernity.
Progressive Muslims are contesting
injustice, exposing violations of human
rights and freedom, standing up to
increasing hegemonic Western political,
economic, and intellectual structures
that perpetuate an unequal distribution
of resources around the world.
Progressive Muslims distinguish
themselves on the one band from
conservative Muslims who adhere to the
authority of the schools of law, and
from neo-conservatives, including
Wahhabis and neo-Wahhabis, the followers
of fourteenth century Muslim Syrian
thinker Ibn Taymiyya and an eighteenth
century Arabian reformer
Muhammad b.
Abdul Wahhab. Safi describes Wahhabi as
a reactionary theological movement based
on a trivial ideology (11). On the other
band, Progressive Muslims distinguish
themselves from secularists and “modemists”,
who look to the prevalent notion of
Western modemity as something to be
imitated and duplicated in toto.
Progressive Muslims
have developed a methodology which is
different from other groups. They call
it “multiple critique”, because it is
critical of bath tradition and
modernity.
For example, veiling or
hijab is not subjugation of women in all
cases (12). In most cases, veiling is
accepted as a strategy of negotiating
the rights to work. “In Iran and Egypt,
for example, as in other parts of the
Muslim world, the wearing of the hijab
has neutralized public space for many
traditional families, thus making it
more acceptable for women to occupy such
space” (13).
CONCLUDING REMARKS
Coming back to the
public discourse on modernity with which
I began this essay, I must note that
this discourse expressed its concern
about not only the Muslim attitude but
also about the Western ambiguity in its
commitment to modernity. The twentieth
century had seen the end of the cold war
and the beginning of a peace process in
the various parts of the world. The
humankind was supposed to be moving in
the twenty first century to an era when
conflicts would be resolved by reasoning
and negotiations, not by use of
violence. No one could expect the 11
September colossal violence against
humanity to happen in this era. Most of
us could not expect a war also. The
perception that Islam was not compatible
with modernity and that the Muslims were
opposed to the values and symbols of
Western civilization, was not sufficient
to justify a war against Muslims. It was
claimed that the war on Afghanistan was
not a war against Islam, but’ it was
still a war. ln spite of this
explanation and despite the fact that
almost all Muslim countries allied with
the USA in this war the image of Islam
as the main obstruction to modernity
looms large. Fortunately, this voice did
not dominate the public discourse this
time.
A considerably sizeable segment
of this discourse remains critical of
how the West, particularly the
government agencies in the United States
have functioned during this time of
crisis. The way the wars were imposed on
Afghanistan and Iraq has damaged the
fragile achievements of modernity. This
criticism has insisted that the resort
to terrorizing the terrorists has only
proved that the West also did not
believe in the values of modernity.
Refusal to negotiate with Afghanistan,
marginalization of the United Nations,
and the use of the extremely destructive
weapons against a country that had been
already devastated by long wars and
against the people who were already on
the verge of extinction by famine, do
not reflect a commitment to the values
of modernity. The culture of modernity
upholds that killing criminals cannot
eliminate crime. That is the reason why
modernity opposes capital punishments.
Islam’s incompatibility with modernity
is also explained on the ground that
Islamic penal law allows corporal
punishments. The discussion in this
public debate urges for investigating
the causes of terrorism in order to
eliminate terrorism. The debate
suggested that terrorism was caused by
the frustration felt on the failure of
political solution. The US hegemonic
foreign policy, especially its
indifference to the political impasse in
the Middle East, contributed to this
frustration. Islam alone cannot be
blamed for the failure of modernity
today.
(1) See R Walzer, “Akhlak”, in The Enç;dopedia cf Islam, New Edition (Leiden, 1986), Vol. 1, pp. 325-329.
(2) Barbara D. Metcalf (Ed.), Moral Candua and Authmit:y, The Place if Adah in South Asian Islam (Berkeley. University of Califomia Press, 1984), especially Brian Silver, “The Adab of Musicians”, pp. 315-329.
(3) See A-M Goichon, “Hayy b. Yakzan”, in The Encyclopedia of Islam, New Edition (Leiden, 1986), Vol. 3, pp. 330-334.
(4) Muhammad Khalid Masud, Shatibi’s Philosophy of Islamic Law (Kuala Lumpur, 2000, Islamabad, 1995), p. 157 ff.
(5) Shah Waliullah, Huiiatullah al-Baligha (Lahore: Maktaba Salafiyya, N.D.).
(6) I would like to mention the following two books written respectively from traditional and liberal perspectives. Abd al Wahhab Abd al-Aziz al-Shishani, Huquq al-insan wa hurriyatihu al-asasiyya fi al-nizam al-Islami wa al-nuzum almu’asara (Rights of man and his basic Freedoms in the Islamic System and the Contemporary Systems, Riyadh: al-Jam’iyyat al-Ilmiyya al-malikiyya, 1980); Ali Abd al-Wahid Wafi, Huquq al-Insan fi’l Islam (Human Rights in Islam, Cairo: Nahda Misr, 1999, sixth edition).
(7) Sishani 1980, 5.
(8) Shishani 1980. 300.
(9) For instance Muhammad Iqbal (d. 1938), a Muslim thinker who influenced Muslim thinking in the subcontinent used the term “reconstruction”. See Muhammad Khalid Masud, Iqb:d’s reconst’Y’tlItian ifljtihad (Lahore: Iqbal Academy, 2003, second edition).
(10) Safi 2003, 2.
(11) Safi 2003, 27 f.n. 3.
(12) Ibid. 151-154.
(13) Ibid. 153, citing Ziba Mir-Hosseini.